Jusletter IT

Legal Taboos

  • Authors: Vytautas Čyras / Friedrich Lachmayer
  • Category: Articles
  • Region: Lithuania, Austria
  • Field of law: Legal Theory
  • Collection: Conference proceedings IRIS 2018
  • Citation: Vytautas Čyras / Friedrich Lachmayer, Legal Taboos, in: Jusletter IT 22 February 2018
The authors formalise a taboo as a prohibition on speaking (informing). Three levels of norms are distinguished. First are basic prohibitions, Forbidden X, i.e. norms which prohibit basic actions, Norm(¬X). Second-level norms comprise primary taboos which prohibit information about facts or fakes, Norm(¬Inf(X)), but permit them to happen. Third-level norms comprise meta-taboos, which prohibit information that a primary taboo exists, Norm(¬Inf(Norm(¬Inf(X)))). A taboo on the essential causes A of an effect E can be officially camouflaged with a fake relationship between certain facts B and E.

Table of contents

  • 1. Introduction
  • 2. Taboo as a Prohibition to Speak
  • 3. Three Levels of Norms on Prohibition
  • 4. Taboo on a Combination of Three Elements of a Relation
  • 5. Related Work
  • 6. Conclusions
  • 7. References

1.

Introduction ^

[1]
The word «taboo» means «a social or religious custom prohibiting or restricting a particular practice or forbidding association with a particular person, place, or thing.»1 «A taboo is a vehement prohibition of an action based on the belief that such behaviour is either too sacred or too accursed for ordinary individuals to undertake.»2 In the fairy tale «The Emperor’s New Clothes», an example of a taboo is the prohibition on the mention that the Emperor is naked.3
[2]
In this paper, a taboo is treated as a prohibition on speaking (in general, informing). In this way, we narrow the broader meaning of a taboo, which is a prohibition on an action. We restrict ourselves to the prohibition of a specific action, namely informing.
[3]
Specifically, a taboo is imposed on giving information about the essential causes of an effect (which is typically evaluated negatively). We assume an effect E, and facts A, B, C that are in a causal relationship with this effect, as denoted by A →c E, B →c E, and C →c E. Suppose A is the main cause, and a taboo is imposed on it, that is, a prohibition on speaking caused by A. We also suppose that the official information is that B causes E, which is fake. This situation is depicted on the left-hand side of Figure 1.
[4]
Taboos can have various meanings and social reasons, such as top-down institutional repression, vertical authoritative power, odd morality, etc. In Figure 1, the green colour denotes entities in the Is realm, blue represents the Ought realm, violet represents power, and yellow represents the content of the information.

Figure 1: The concept of taboo in context

[5]
Definition. The concept of a taboo is briefly overviewed by Duschinsky [2014], who finds that nowadays taboo is not an exotic word.4 Duschinsky notes that according to Freud, «The meaning of «taboo», as we see it, diverges in two contrary directions. To us it means, on the one hand, «sacred» or «consecrated», and on the other «uncanny», «dangerous», «forbidden», «unclean» [Freud 2001, 18]. In his book Taboo [1956, 22], Franz Steiner studies the subject from the perspective of sociology (or, more precisely, social anthropology). Taboos refer to danger.5 Steiner notes that to make a comparative category the definition of taboo is narrowed (Steiner 1956, 121). Next Steiner refers to Margaret Mead’s article «Tabu» in Encyclopaedia of Social Sciences, 1937: «Tabu may be defined as a negative sanction, a prohibition whose infringement results in an automatic penalty without human or superhuman mediation.»
[6]
Taboos may be sensitive from several perspectives: morally, religiously, culturally, socially, politically, and also legally. Taboo norms can be evaluated negatively, although various positions can be explored. Broyde [2002] discusses three different problems: informing a bandit, informing an abusive government, and informing a (procedurally) just system of government. The view «No prohibition to inform when government is just» has a place in a discussion [Broyde 2002]. We further focus on formalising statements about taboo; explorations of the function of taboos and social reasons are set aside.6

2.

Taboo as a Prohibition to Speak ^

[7]
Let us denote by Inf (X) that information about X exists (in reality or in a model such as a database). For example, information that A causes E is denoted by Inf (A →c E). Let us follow the notation in deontic logic and denote that it is forbidden that X by F X or F(X). The obligatoriness of X is denoted by O X and the permissibility of X is denoted by P X. The prohibition F X can be defined as O ¬X (obligatory to omit X, i.e. it is obligatory to not do X) or ¬P X (no permission to do X).
[8]
We start by defining taboo as a prohibition to speak. Thus, a restriction is imposed on a general prohibition F X of any action X. Taboo means that a phenomenon X may be permitted, but informing about X is prohibited. An example is a taboo on genitals: «In our family, it is forbidden to speak about genitals». However, it is not forbidden to have genitals. This is represented as Taboo(genitals). Similarly, at a party, it is forbidden to speak about money. However, it is not forbidden to have money. This is represented as Taboo(money).
[9]
A taboo can be expressed with a formula in modal logic:

T X = def F Inf (X)

[10]

where T is treated as a modal operator that is syntactically analogical to the deontic operators O, P and F. Formalisation of normativity implies a norm as an entity. A taboo on X means a norm that prohibits informing about X:

Taboo(X) = def N(¬Inf (X))

(1)

[11]

In our formalisation, all the entities, including actions, facts and norms, exist as truth (true or false) in the realm of science, i.e. in a model such as a database. Norms N(•) correspond to the Ought realm or its representation in the model, while Inf corresponds to the Is realm.

[12]
A norm N(A) must be assigned certain semantics. Consider N(A) as a commandment to do A and N(¬A) as a prohibition on doing A. The relation between a norm (rule) and the normative status of the duty can be explored; see [Lachmayer 1977, 75–76]:

N(A) → O(A) – From a commandment, an obligatory duty arises

N(¬A) → O(¬A) – From a prohibition, a prohibitive duty arises.

[13]

Meta-taboo. Next we strengthen the above definition with a double prohibition called a meta-taboo. A meta-taboo is a prohibition on informing that there is norm that prohibits speaking about X:

Meta-taboo (X) = def N(¬Inf (N(¬Inf(X))))

(2)

[14]
In a literal sense, a meta-taboo can be linked with the expression «taboo on the mention of taboo», which is used in the literature; cf. Attridge [2014].7

3.

Three Levels of Norms on Prohibition ^

[15]
Consider a language L for expressing statements about facts, fake facts and taboos. Fake facts can be formalised as statements with false content. Thus, basic entities can be Fact (denoted by FC) or Fake (denoted by FK). The reference area of L sentences (formulae) comprises more entities. Firstly there is Meaning (ME); then relations, such as Causality (c), Telos (te), Equality (=), and Transformation (tr ); see Figure 2. The relations hold between the entities and express the semantics of L.

Figure 2: Basic entities to which norms refer

[16]
Norms 1. The next entity within L is a norm (denoted by N). There are several levels of norms. The first level (Norms 1) comprises norms about facts, N1(FC), and fakes, N1(FK); see Figure 3. The following are examples of cases which can be created:
  1. N1(FC) means a commandment to establish a fact FC. For instance, N(door_closed), represents a commandment to close the door. Closing the door is a compliant action. This type of norm refers to Fact; see Figure 3.
  2. N1(¬FC) means a prohibition of a fact FC. For instance, N(¬door_closed), means a prohibition on closing the door. Opening the door is a compliant action. This type of norm also refers to Fact.
  3. N1(FK) means a commandment to establish a fake FK. As an example, imagine a community of liars. This type of norm refers to Fake.
  4. N1(¬FK) means a prohibition of a fake. This is a normal case. In general, fake facts are prohibited. For instance, news with false content is prohibited; the use of counterfeit money is also prohibited. This type of norm refers to Fake.
  5. ¬N1(FC) means an absence of commandment to establish a fact FC. We hold that an absence of a norm about a fact weakly implies a norm about a fake. As an example, we suppose a world with one door, and suppose that the door is closed. Hence, the proposition «‹The door is closedis a fact» is true. Suppose that ¬N1(door_closed) holds in this world. The latter means the absence of any commandment to close the door. Next, suppose a fake news report of «The door is opened». However, nobody is obliged to react to this fake, because of the absence of any commandment to close the door. In this sense, the fake is compliant in this world. Therefore we hold that the type ¬N1(FC) refers to Fake.
[17]
We do not explore case 5. It is important only to focus on cases 1 and 2, which refer to Fact, and cases 3 and 4, which refer to Fake.

Figure 3: Types of norms at the first level, Norms 1, and their references

[18]
Info 1 and Norms 2. Information is next entity in L to be explored. Information about X is denoted by Inf(X). More precisely, the latter means the output of an act of informing about X. Information is primarily about facts, fakes and norms. The first-level information, Info 1, firstly comprises informing that FC exists as a fact, denoted by Inf 1(FC), or, secondly, informing that FK exists as a fake, denoted by Inf 1(FK); see link (i) in Figure 4. This can be treated as follows. Given a (news) statement X, the act of informing Inf 1 produces a flag (or a tag) which means that X is either of true content (thus assigning X to Facts) or false content (thus assigning X to Fakes).

Figure 4: Primitive taboos (Norms 2) and Info 1 added to Figure 3

[19]

Second-level norms, Norms 2, formalise primitive taboos; see Figure 4. Here, norms are of the type

N 2(¬Inf 1(FK))

(3)

[20]
This means a prohibition N 2 to inform that FK is a fake; see link (ii) in Figure 4. Hence, Norms 2 secure fakes. Note that Equation (3) above coincides with the right-hand side of Equation (1) after substituting X with FK. Fakes flourish (on the basic level) because they are secured by Norms 2. Recall «All that is necessary for the triumph of evil is that good men do nothing.» (https://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Edmund_Burke). Therefore Norms 2 can be evaluated as evil.
[21]
Info 2 and Norms 3: Meta-taboo. The second level of information, Info 2, consists of information about primitive taboos; see link (iii) in Figure 5. Indeed, Inf 2(N 2(¬Inf 1(FK)) means an act of informing that a prohibition N 2 exists against informing Inf 1 that a fake FK exists.
[22]

The third-level norms, Norms 3, formalise meta-taboos. Here the norms are of type N 3(¬Inf 2(•)). This means a prohibition N 3 on informing Inf 2 about anything; see link (iv) in Figure 5. Specifically, Norms 3 comprise a prohibition N 3 to inform, Info 2, that a prohibition N 2 exists to inform, Info 1, that a fake FK exists. Thus a meta-taboo secures a primitive taboo; see the top-down path (iv)–(iii)–(ii)–(i) in Figure 5.

[23]
Taboo on Fact. Taboo on fact and taboo on fake form a duality. A taboo on a fact FC, denoted by Taboo(FC), means a prohibition on informing that FC holds as a fact. The proof is based on the idea that FC being a fact implies that ¬FC is a fake. Indeed, the content of FC being true implies that the content of ¬FC is false. Let us apply the taboo on fakes, Equation (3), and substitute FK with ¬FC to obtain N 2(¬Inf 1(¬FC)); this reads «A prohibition to inform that ¬FC is a fake». This is equivalent to reading «A prohibition to inform that FC is a fact». This paragraph explains the definition of Taboo (1).
[24]
Example. In the fairy tale, a fact is that the emperor is naked. A taboo is formally imposed on this fact as:

N 2(¬Inf 1(«The emperor is naked» is a fact))

[25]
Dually, a fake is that the emperor is wearing new clothes. A taboo is formally imposed on this fake as:

N 2(¬Inf 1(«The emperor is wearing new clothes» is a fake))

[26]
Taboo on Any Basic Entity. Above, we have explored the taboo on fakes and facts. A taboo can also be imposed on other basic entities, such as the causal relation between facts, teleology of actions, equality of meaning of facts, transformation of meaning, etc.

Figure 5: Meta-taboos Norms 3 and Info 2 added to Figure 4

4.

Taboo on a Combination of Three Elements of a Relation ^

[27]

In mathematics, a binary relation R between two sets S1 and S2 is defined as a subset of a Cartesian product R⊂ S1×S2. For any xS1 and yS2 we write xRy to abbreviate (x,y)R. Elements of the set R are pairs (x,y). A binary relation can be represented with a two-column table.

[28]
Several meanings can be assigned to a taboo on the causal relation A →c E between a fact A and an effect E. The original meaning is a prohibition to inform that A causes E. The second idea is a prohibition to inform about the fact A only, Taboo(A). The third meaning is a prohibition to inform about the effect E, Taboo(E), and fourthly, a prohibition to inform about the causality relationship c (its intentional description), Taboo(→c). The last meaning appears, for example, in the case of a fake official version that the relation A →c E is accidental or a correlation, in other words, the causality →c is simply a mystery of faith (mysterium fidei).
[29]
The last taboo, Taboo(→c), can appear, for example, in a network of facts, effects and other entities, such as actions, goals, teleological relations, etc. Suppose a taboo exists on the relation A – c E –. To camouflage this taboo, a teleological relation B + →te G + can be introduced, where the goal G + is evaluated positively (Figure 6). Additionally, a fake official version can be introduced that the effect E – is caused by a certain fact B +.

Figure 6: A taboo on a causal relationship A – c E – is camouflaged in three steps, with a teleological relation te between B + and a certain goal G +, which is evaluated positively: 1) in fact, both A – and E – are evaluated negatively; 2) therefore, the official version is announced that a certain cause B +, which is evaluated positively, causes E –; 3) a camouflage is that B + serves a good goal G +, which outweighs E –

5.

Related Work ^

[30]
We have modelled the meaning of Andersens fable as a taboo on speaking that the emperor is naked. This tale illustrates the phenomenon of pluralistic ignorance, which defined as a situation where «no one believes, but everyone thinks that everyone else believes» and is mainly studied in social psychology. Hansen [2011] describes pluralistic ignorance as «the phenomenon where a group of people shares a false belief about the beliefs, norms, actions or thoughts of the other group members» and formalises it using epistemic/doxastic logic (based on plausibility models). Hansen focuses on the question of what it takes to dissolve the phenomenon, and talks about the dynamics of knowledge and beliefs of a group of agents. Public announcements are the simplest form of actions. In addition to Andersen’s fable, Hansen provides classical examples including the «questions in a classroom».8 Hansen formulates examples in terms of beliefs, but notes that pluralistic ignorance is often defined in terms of norms, e.g. «a situation where a majority of group members privately reject a norm, but assume (incorrectly) that most others accept it»; see [Centola et al. 2005]. The latter also note that «It is not hard to find everyday examples of this fable in the academic kingdom. We can all think of prestigious scholars who are widely proclaimed as having the most brilliant new ideas, yet privately, people find the work entirely incomprehensible». Centola et al. study the «willingness to feign support for a public lie» and provide further examples.9
[31]
We would model the classroom example with a primitive taboo on questions, i.e. a norm that prohibits students from saying that they have questions. The fact is that students do have questions.

6.

Conclusions ^

[32]
Modelling taboo in the legal domain gives rise to a terminological framework, which is depicted in Figure 5. This paper singles out three levels of norms and two levels of information. We introduce the terms «primitive taboo» and «meta-taboo», which secures the former.

7.

References ^

Attridge, John, «A Taboo on the Mention of Taboo»: Taciturnity and Englishness in Parade’s End and André Maurois» Les Silences Du Colonel Bramble. International Ford Madox Ford Studies 2014, vol. 13, 23–35.

Broyde, Michael J., Informing on others for violating American law: a Jewish law view. Journal of Halacha and Contemporary Society 2002. http://www.jlaw.com/Articles/mesiralaw2.html.

Centola, Damon/Willer, Robb/Macy, Michael, The emperor’s dilemma: a computational model of self-enforcing norms. American Journal of Sociology 2014, 110(4), 1009–1040. http://ndg.asc.upenn.edu/wp-content/uploads/2016/04/Centola-et-al-2005-AJS.pdf, 2005.

Duschinsky, Robbie, Taboo, overview. In: Teo, Thomas (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Critical Psychology, pp. 1921–1923. Springer, New York 2014.

Freud, Sigmund, Totem and Taboo, Routledge, 2001 [1919] (Totem und Tabu, 1913).

Hansen, Jens Ulrik, A logic-based approach to pluralistic ignorance. In: Academia.edu 2011. http://www.academia.edu/1894486/A_Logic-Based_Approach_to_Pluralistic_Ignorance.

Lachmayer, Friedrich, Grundzüge einer Normentheorie: Zur Struktur der Normen dargestellt am Beispiel des Rechtes. Duncker und Humblot, Berlin 1977.

Prentice, Deborah A./Miller, Dale T., Pluralistic ignorance and alcohol use on campus: Some consequences of misperceiving the social norm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 1993, 64(2), 243–256.

Steiner, Franz, Taboo. Cohen & West, London 1956.

  1. 1 The Oxford Dictionary, https://en.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/taboo (all websites last accessed on 1 January 2018).
  2. 2 See Wikipedia, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Taboo and Encyclopædia Britannica Online, «Taboo». Common taboos involve restrictions on or ritual regulations for killing and hunting; sex and sexual relationships; reproduction; the dead and their graves; and food and dining (primarily cannibalism).
  3. 3 Danish author Hans Christian Andersen wrote about two weavers who promise an emperor a new suit of clothes, which they say is invisible to those who are unfit for their positions, stupid, or incompetent. When the Emperor parades before his subjects in his new clothes, no one dares to say that they don’t see any suit of clothes on him for fear that they will be seen as «unfit for their positions, stupid, or incompetent». Finally, a child cries out, «But he isn’t wearing anything at all!» The story is about a situation where «no one believes, but everyone believes that everyone else believes. Or alternatively, everyone is ignorant as to whether or not the Emperor has clothes, but believes that everyone else is not ignorant.» [Hansen 2011]; see Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Emperor’s_New_Clothes.
  4. 4 Duschinsky begins with the following definition: «‹Taboo› is a Polynesian term, which has come to refer in Western academic and public discourses to topics, spaces, or practices that are consecrated as prohibited or to the process itself of marking them off» [Duschinsky 2014].
  5. 5 Steiner defines: «Taboo is concerned (1) with all the social mechanisms of obedience which have ritual significance; (2) with specific and restrictive behaviour in dangerous situations. One might say that taboo deals with the sociology of danger itself, for it is also concerned (3) with the protection of individuals who are in danger, and (4) with the protection of the society from those endangered – and therefore dangerous – persons… [T]aboo is an element of all those situations in which attitudes to values are expressed in terms of danger behaviour» [Steiner 1956, 20–21].
  6. 6 Centola et al. write: «It is easy to explain why people comply with unpopular norms – they fear social sanctions. And it is easy to explain why people pressure others to behave the way they want them to behave. But why pressure others to do the opposite? Why would people publicly enforce a norm that they secretly wish would go away?» [Centola et al. 2005].
  7. 7 John Attridge [2014] writes about the depiction of Englishness in novels. He notes that it was Archibald Lyall who called the «taboo on the mention of taboo›, in his 1930 book «It Isn’t Done, or, the Future of Taboo Among the British Islanders».
  8. 8 «[T]he classroom example in which, after having presented the students with difficult material, the teacher asks them whether they have any questions. Even though most students do not understand the material they may not ask any questions. All the students interpret the lack of questions from the other students as a sign that they understood the material, and to avoid being publicly displayed as the stupid one, they dare not ask questions themselves. In this case the students are ignorant with respect to some facts, but believe that the rest of the students are not ignorant about the facts.» [Hansen 2011]
  9. 9 «It is not difficult to find other familiar examples of compliance with, and enforcement of, privately unpopular norms: 1. the exposure of the ‹politically incorrect› by the righteously indignant who thereby affirm their own moral integrity; 2. gossiping about a social faux pas by snobs anxious to affirm their own cultural sophistication; 3. public adoration of a bully by fearful schoolboys who do not want to become the next victim; 4. ‹luxury fever› (Frank 2000) among status seekers who purchase $50 cigars, $17,000 wristwatches, and $3 million bras, in an arms race of conspicuous consumption and one-upmanship that leaves the contestants no happier but perhaps a bit less affluent.» [Centola et al. 2005]