1.
Introduction ^
2.
The Traditional Legal Theories on the Structure of Laws ^
Hans Kelsen regards legal norms, which is to be conceived as meaning of legal sentences, as an object of scientific cognition of law and tries to develop a theory to clarify the system of legal norms.
Kelsen understands the legal norm as «a hypothetical judgment that expresses the specific linking of a conditioning material fact with a conditioned consequence». Thus, the legal norm becomes the law-sentence (Rechtssatz), which shows the basic form of statutes.1
According to Kelsen, law consists of primary norms and secondary norms. Kelsen defines these as follows: primary norms are norms which describe: «under the condition of the opposite behavior, a coercive act should be occurred as consequence». The norm establishing a sanction-avoiding behavior would be a secondary legal norm.2 Kelsen considers the sanction as an essential element of law. Therefore, he regards legal norms which regulate people’s behaviors as secondary norms and legal norms which regulate sanctions given to the people who breach the relevant secondary norms as primary norms.
H.L.A. Hart tries to clarify the concept and structure of law in terms of internal and external aspects on the one hand, and primary and secondary rules on the other hand. The observer’s view of a set of rules is based on an external aspect and the view of members who accept and use those rules belongs to the internal aspect. Through his introduction of the internal aspect, Hart enables us to explain law not simply to be sanction-threatening but rather obligation-imposing.3 According to Hart, «while primary rules are concerned with the actions that individuals must or must not do, these secondary rules are all concerned with the primary rules themselves.4 They specify the ways in which the primary rules may be conclusively ascertained, introduced, eliminated and varied and the fact of their violation conclusively determined.»5 He explains law as the union of primary and secondary rules.6 Thus, Hart has made great contributions to the clarification of the structure of law. However, his analysis remains a rough descriptive-sociological analysis of people’s behaviors related to legal rules. It lacks a precise linguistic or logical analysis of legal rule sentences as linguistic objects and their mutual relations. Thus, a precise linguistic and logical analysis of the structure of law, that Hart’s theory would suggest with his conception of primary and secondary rules and their union, is needed to enable us to develop a total system of legal reasoning in the future society. This will be addressed in this paper in terms of LJ.
3.
The Internal Structure of Legal Sentences – Three Fundamental Alternative Sorts of Legal Sentences ^
3.1.
Legal Rule and Fact Sentences ^
∀X(a (X) ← b (X)).7
∀X(legal_consequence(X) ← legal_requirement(X))
b(x1).
legal_requirement(x1)).
3.2.
Legal Element and Complex Sentences ^
Legal element sentences mark the minimal units of legal sentences, whereas complex legal sentences are the combination of legal sentences, typically with a unique name for the whole. For example, «A contract is concluded at the moment when an acceptance of an offer becomes effective» (Article 23 of the United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods [CISG]) is a legal element sentence. The CISG itself, its parts, its chapters, most of its articles are legal complex sentences. The internal logical structure of legal element sentences and the complex legal sentence in the above example can be represented as follows:8
cisg_article(23): is_concluded(_,[contract(C,[A,B,M,S]),T]) ←
become_effective(_,[acceptance(Ac,[A,B,Of,S2]),T]) &
is_effective(_,[offer(Of,[A,B,S1]),T1]).9
cisg: complex_sentence(cisg,[
part(part1,[…]),
part(part2,[article(14,[(1),(2)]),…, article(23)],…, article(29,[(1),(2)])]),
part(part3,[…]),
part(part4,[…])])
3.3.
Legal Object and Meta Sentences ^
is_obligatory(Person,Action).11
is_obligatory(‘Bernard’,pay(‘Bernard’, ‘Anzai’, price($50,000,goods), t22_02_2018).12
∀X,Z(is_obligatory(X,Z) ←
person( X) & action(Z)).
∀X,(is_obligatory(X,Z) ←
buyer(X, sale(S, X,Y,G)) & pay(Z,X,seller(Y,S),price(P,G))).14
is_valid(s1,23_02_2017).
become_valid((s1,23_02_2016).
become_null((s1,23_02_2018).
[r0]:∀S∀T(is_valid(S,T)← →
become_valid(S,T1) & before_or_same_time(T1,T) &
not((become_null(S,T2]) & before_or_same_time(T2,T)))).
In positive laws, we can find many legal rule sentences which determine if sentences become valid or become null (or is terminated). However, we cannot find any legal rule sentence which directly determines if a sentence is valid or not. Through the analysis of positive laws and the construction of legal reasoning systems, the author has found the legal meta-rule sentence [r0] above. Whenever the validity of a legal sentence is questioned, this rule sentence is implicitly applied to determine whether the legal sentence is valid16. In this sense, this meta-rule sentence is to be called as the Most Fundamental Legal Meta-Rule Sentence (MFLMRS). To determine whether the first requirement of this rule sentence «become_valid(S,T1)» and the second requirement «become_null(S,T2)» are true, there are several implicit fundamental legal meta-rule sentences and a great number of positive legal meta-rule sentences. The further examples will be presented in the next chapter.
4.
The External Structure of Legal Sentences – the Union of Legal Sentences ^
∀X(a(X)←b(X)).
∀X(a(X)c(X))., or
∀X(a(X)←b(X)) &∀X(a(X)←c(X)).
4.1.
The Union of Legal Rule and Fact Sentences ^
The logical union of a certain type of legal rule and fact sentences realizes a logical inference automatically when they are located in the practitioner’s memory or in the computer software memory like Prolog in legal reasoning systems:
(1) ∀X{a(X)←b(X)}
(2) b(x1)
--------------------
(3) a(x1)
4.2.
The Union of Legal Element and Complex Sentences ^
Legal element sentences are united as a group in a legal complex sentence and legal element sentences in a legal complex sentence can be treated at once in the application of the relevant legal meta-rule sentences. The examples of such legal meta-rule sentences will be presented later as the r01 and r02.
4.3.
The Union of Legal Object and Meta Sentences ^
[s1]: A must pay $55,000 to B by February 23, 2018.
[s2]: ‘A must pay $55,000 to B by February 23, 2018’ is valid on January 20, 2018.
[s1]: must(‘A’,pay(‘A’, $55,000,B,time(T,by(23_02_2018))).
[s2]: is_valid(must(‘A’,pay(‘A’, $55,000,B,time_by(T,23_02_2018)),time(20_01_2018)).
[s2]: is_valid(s1,time(20_01_2018)).
[r01] A legal element sentence S becomes valid at time T, if
S is an element sentence of legal complex sentence CS, and
legal complex sentence CS becomes valid at time T.
[3AA1]: A legal complex sentence becomes valid at time T, if
the legal complex sentence is formed at time T1 and T1 is before or at the same time as T, and
it is not the case that the complex sentence is invalid, and
((the complex sentence entails the beginning time of effectiveness and
the beginning time has come at T) or
(the complex sentence entails a condition of the effectiveness and
the condition is fulfilled at time T)) or
T is T1).
[CISG Article 23]: «A contract is concluded at the moment when an acceptance of an offer becomes effective in accordance with the provisions of this Convention.»
[The Constitution of Japan Article 59] «A bill becomes a law on passage by both Houses, except as otherwise provided by the Constitution.»
[The Constitution of Japan Article 98] This Constitution shall be the supreme law of the nation and no law, ordinance, imperial rescript or other act of government, or part thereof, contrary to the provisions hereof, shall have legal force or validity.
[Civil Code Article 90] A juristic act with any purpose which is against public policy is void.
In some cases, a legal element sentence alone becomes valid independently from a complex sentence. One of them is the fundamental legal meta-rule sentence regulating the relation between rights and duties. The following meta-rule sentences must be implicitly valid as a fundamental legal meta-rule sentence in the legal world. Positive laws have been issued on the assumption that this rule sentence is valid:
[3aa2]: «B must do Z» becomes valid at time T, if
«A may require B to do Z» is valid at T &
A requires B to do Z at T.19
[r02]: A legal sentence becomes null if
it is an element sentence of a complex sentence and
the complex sentence becomes null.22
[r02-2]: A contract becomes null, if
the contract is avoided.
[mr4b]: A legal sentence ‘B must do Z’ becomes null at time T, if
B performs the action Z at T.
4.4.
The Union of Legal Meta Sentences and other Legal Meta Sentences ^
is_valid(r0,T). is_valid(r01,T). is_valid(3aa1,T). is_valid(3aa2,T). is_valid(r02,T).23
5.
Concluding Remarks ^
6.
Acknowledgement ^
This paper was written by the author during his study as a visiting professor at the Hermann-Kantorowicz-Institute and the Institute of Business and Tax Law of the University of Kiel Faculty of Law. The author thanks his host professor Robert Alexy as well as his colleagues Ino Augsberg, Rudolf Meyer-Pritzl, Joachim Jickeli and Michael Stöber for their kind supports. The author thanks his student assistant Regina Kardel for her assistance to the author's study of this paper. She especially contributed to writing the chapter 2.
- 1 Kelsen (note 1).
- 2 Kelsen (note 1), p. 30. English translation (not 1), p. 30.
- 3 Shapiro, Scott J., What is the Internal Point of View?, Faculty Scholarship Series, 200,. Paper 1336, p. 1157. It is good that Shapiro highly evaluates Hart’s internal aspect because it enables the character of legal rules (not merely as sanction-affording but) obligation-imposing. However, we notice that the sanction-affording aspect is essential for laws in comparison with morals on the one hand and that the sanction-affording rules can and should be reduced to the obligation-imposing on the other hand.
- 4 That secondary rules are concerned with primary rules themselves means that the former are meta-rules of the latter rules. However, it is a pity that H.L.A. Hart does not refer to the nature of secondary rules as meta-rules.
- 5 Hart, H.L.A., The concept of law, 2nd edition, Oxford University Press 1994, p. 80.
- 6 Hart (note 6), p. 82–92.
- 7 This is a predicate logical formula in which a variable is to be represented in a capital letter.
- 8 This formula is a CPF. CPF is the abbreviation of Compound Predicate Formula, which is a logical representation developed by the author for his legal reasoning systems. As regards the foundation of CPF, see: Yoshino, Hajime, On the Logical Foundation of Compound Predicate Formulae for Legal Knowledge Representation, in: Artificial Intelligence and Law, Vol. 5, No. 1–2 1997, pp. 77–96. For a simple explanation of CPF: see: Sakurai, Seichiro/Yoshino, Hajime, Identification of Implicit Legal Requirements with Legal Abstract Knowledge, in: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, 1993, pp. 298–305. All variables used in this formula are bound by universal quantifiers which are eliminated.
- 9 In this rule, «the offer is effective» is set as its second requirement. The CISG article 23 itself does not directly express that «the offer is effective» is a requirement for a contract to be concluded. Through a creative systematic reasoning from the related articles, this requirement is added in this representation of the rule. Cf.: Sakurai/Yoshino (note 9).
- 10 The predicate is not restricted to the noun «obligation.» Other predicates which represent the conception of the obligation are available, e.g., «is obligatory,» «must,» «has to,» and so on.
- 11 «Person» is used for a variable assigned to an item of person and «Action» to an item of action.
- 12 This formula to be read: «It is obligatory for Bernard to pay Anzai the price of goods $50,000 on February 22nd 2018.»
- 13 This is the approach in which the deontic term «obligatory» is represented with a predicate. We think that «Deontic Logic» is not necessary to logically formalize legal rule sentences.
- 14 This formula is to be read as follows: «If X is a buyer of the sale S of goods G between X and Y and Z is to pay the seller Y the price P, then it is obligatory for X to do Z.»
- 15 The predicate is not restricted to the noun «validity.» Other predicates which represent the conception of the validity are available, e.g., «is valid,» «is become valid,» «become null,» «is terminated,» and so on
- 16 People apply rules to a problem usually without checking the validity of the rules because they believe it or presuppose that the relevant rules are valid. However, to put it precisely, one should always check whether the rule is valid whenever one applies a rule. This will be necessary especially for a computer based legal reasoning.
- 17 To save space in the paper, in the following, not predicate logical formulae but their natural language representations will be given to express the relevant rule sentences.
- 18 It is important to differentiate the concept of formation of law from the validity of law.
- 19 In this rule sentence «may» can be replaced by «can» without changing its meaning.
- 20 Hart (note 2), p. 81.
- 21 To execute a right means to issue a legal sentence which makes the relevant legal sentence legally valid or invalid.
- 22 The term «become null» is a technical term introduced here. Usually «is terminated» is used. These are synonyms.
- 23 «T» is a variable so that it represents the relevant rule sentence is valid at any time.
- 24 The author has once presented a small paper on this topic for AI and Law community. Cf. Yoshino, Hajime, The Systematization of Law in Terms of the Validity, in: Procedings of the Thirteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, 2011, pp. 121–125. A deep legal theoretical analysis and discussion with real examples should be provided for legal theory communities as a future task.