1.
Introduction ^
2.
The concepts of legal sentences ^
2.1.
Legal rule and fact sentences ^
a(X)<-b(X), c(X,Y). 3
b(x1). c(x1,y1).
2.2.
Legal object and meta-sentences ^
CISG Article 99 (1): This Convention enters into force, ... , on the first day of the month following the expiration of twelve months after the date of deposit of the tenth instrument of ratification, acceptance, approval or accession, ... .
3.
Fundamental legal meta-sentences ^
3.1.
The most fundamental meta-rule sentence ^
[r0] A legal sentence is valid at time T, if and only if
the legal sentence becomes valid at time T1 before T &
it is not the case that the sentence becomes null at time T2 before T.
3.2.
Fundamental meta-rule sentences regulating the relation between rights and duties ^
[3aa2] A legal sentence 'X has an obligation to do Z at time T1' becomes valid at time T, if
Y exercises the right to require X to do Z at time T1 at time T &
the legal sentence 'Y has a right to require X to do Z at time T1' is valid at time T.
4.
Case problem ^
5.
Analysis of changes of legal rights and duties relations ^
5.1.
Phases of the change of the validity of legal sentences through the exercise of rights ^
5.2.
The occurrence of the obligation to repair the goods ^
Article 46 (3) If the goods do not conform with the contract, the buyer may require the seller to remedy the lack of conformity by repair, … .
On the basis of fact (9), the first requirement of the applied rule sentence [3aa2] is proven as:
B required A on September 1to repair the lack of conformity of goods by repair by October 1.
„B has the right to A on September 1 to require B to repair the lack of conformity by repair by October 1“ is valid on September 1.
„B has right to require A to repair the lack of conformity by repair by October 1“becomes valid on September 1.
6.
Implementation of the reasoning of the relationship between rights and duties ^
6.1.
CPF as a logical representation method of legal knowledge ^
predicate(ID,CaseList)
6.2.
Representations of fundamental legal meta-rule sentences ^
[r0]14 is_valid(IV,[S, T])<-
become_valid(BV,[S, T1]) & before(T1,T) &
not((become_null(BN,[S, T2]),before(T2,T))) 15
[r3aa2] become_valid(BV,[obligation(RE,[ X,Y,Z]),T])<-
exercise(EX,[Y,right(RE,[Y,X,require(RE,[Y,X,Z,T])]),T]) &
is_valid(IV,[right(RI,[Y ,X,require(RE,[B,A,Z,T])])]),T])
[mf0]: is_valid(_,[r0,T]). [mf3aa2]: is_valid(_,[r3aa2,T]).
exercise(ex,['B',right(r,['B','A',require(rq,[buyer(bu,['B']),seller(se,['A']),remedy(rm,['A',the_lack_of_conformity(lc,[Goods,Contract]),repair(rp,['A‘,Goods ,by(t10_01)]),by(t10_01)]),t09_01])]),t09_01]).
6.3.
Meta-inference engine ^
(1) solve(A):- sen(S,[A]).
(2) solve(not(A)):-not(solve(A)).
(3) solve(A&B):-solve(A),solve(B).
(4) solve(A;B):-solve(A);solve(B).
(5) solve(A):-
(6) sen(S,[A<- B]),
(7) solve(B),
………
(11) get_time_of_event(A,T),
(12) solve(is_valid(I,[S,T])).
6.4.
Demonstration of inferring an obligation from the exercise of a right ^
is_valid(IV,[obligation(OB,[‘A’,‘B’,Z])]),t09_15])
become_valid(V,[obligation(OB,[‘A’,‘B’,Z])]),T1])&before(T1,t09_15)¬((become_null(BN,[S,T2]),before(T2, t09_15)))
become_valid(BV,[obligation(Id1,[‘A’, ‘B’,Z])]),T1])&before(T1,t09_15)
not((become_null(BN,[S,T2]),before(T2, t09_15)))
exercise(ex,['B',right(r,['B','A',require(rq,[buyer(bu,['B']),seller(se,['A']),remedy(rm,['A',the_lack_of_conformity(lc,[Goods,Contract]),repair(rp,['A‘,Goods ,by(t10_01)]),by(t10_01)]),t09_01])]),t09_01]).
is_valid(IV,[right(r,['B','A',require(rq,[buyer(bu,['B']),seller(se,['A']),remedy(rm,['A',the_lack_of_conformity(lc,[Goods,Contract]),repair(rp,['A‘,Goods ,by(t10_01)]),by(t10_01)]),t09_01])])]), t09_01])
is_valid(IV,[obligation(Id1,[‘A’,‘B’, remedy(RE,['A',the_lack_of_conformity(LOC,[Goods,Contract]),
repair(REP,[A,Goods ,by(t10_01)]),by(t10_01)])]),t09_15])
7.
Conclusion ^
9.
References ^
Allen, L.E. & Saxon, C.S., A-Hohfeld: A Language for Robust Structural Representation of Knowledge in the Legal Domain to Build Interpretation-Assistance Expert Systems. In: Meyer, J. Ch., Wieringa, J. (eds.), Deontic Logic in Computer Science: Normative System Specification, Wiley & Sons, pp. 205–224 (1993).
Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law, Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 97–120 (1961).
Hohfeld, W. N., Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning. Yale Law Journal 23, pp. 16–59 (1913).
Kelsen, H., Reine Rechtslehre, 2. Auflage, Verlag Franz Deuticke, Wien (1960); Studienausgage der 1. Auflage 1934, Mohr Siebeck (2008).
Raz, J., The Concept of a Legal System, 2nd. Ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 93–208 (1980).
Sergot, M., et al., The British Nationality Act as a Logic Program. In: Communications of the ACM, Vol.29, No.5, pp. 370-386 (1986).
Yoshino, H., & Sakurai, S., Identification of Implicit Legal Requirements with Legal Abstract Knowledge. In: Proc. The Fourth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, pp. 298–305 (1993).
Yoshino, H., The Systematization of Legal Meta-inference. In: Proc. The Fifth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, pp. 266-275 (1995).
Yoshino, H., On the Logical Foundation of Compound Predicate Formulae for Legal Knowledge Representation. In: Artificial Intelligence and Law, Vol.5, Nos.1–2, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht /Boston /London, pp. 77–96 (1997).
Yoshino, H., Logical Structure of Contract Law System – For Constructing a Knowledge Base of the United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods. In: Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence, Vol.2 No1, Fuji Technology Press, Tokyo, pp. 2–11 (1998).
Yoshino, H., Tractatus Logico-Juridicus – Its Basis, In: Jakob, R., Philipps, L., Schweighofer, E., Varga, C. (Hrsg.), Auf dem Weg zur Idee der Gerechtigkeit: Gedenkschrift für Ilmar Tammelo, LIT, Wien, pp. 127–148 (2009).
Yoshino, H., The Systematization of Law in Terms of the Validity. In: Proc. Thirteenth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, pp121–125 (2011).
- 1 Hohfeld considered: if X has a right against Y that he shall stay off the former’s land, the correlative (and equivalent) is that Y is under a duty toward X to stay off the place. See: Hohfeld (1913), pp. 32f. Allen and Saxon have tried to formalize this relation logically. See: Allen & Saxon (1993), pp 205-224.
- 2 As regards Logical Jurisprudence, see: Yoshino (2009) pp. 124-148.
- 3 This formula is a simplified logic programming expression. This could be read for example: “For all X, X becomes effective, if X is an offer and X reaches the offeree.” This formula could correspond to CISG Article 15(1) which says: “An offer becomes effective when it reaches the offeree.” CISG is an abbreviation of United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods. “<-“ in the formula is interpreted by our inference engine as “:-“ in Prolog (see: chapter 6.3, line 5-7).
- 4 These formulas could be read for example: “x1 is Anzai’s offer and it reaches Barnard on April 5th”.
- 5 We agree with Hans Kelsen in that the concept of obligation is essential for law. People try to act in accordance with their legal obligations prescribed by law. In this manner, law helps to control human behavior and realize order in society. We consider obligation is the object of the legal world.
- 6 This most fundamental meta-rule sentence was discovered by us using the event calculus approach during the construction of the knowledge bases of CISG. For more information on event calculus, see: Sergot (1986).
- 7 Kelsen (2008), pp. 61-63.
- 8 Hart (1961), pp. 40f., pp. 78f., pp. 92-94.
- 9 It is to be noted that legal object sentences become valid not only by the execution of rights. There are many legal rule sentences directly regulating the obligation of addressees. It is also to be noted that legal meta-sentences describing rights regulate not only the validity of legal object sentences but also the validity of legal meta-sentences.
- 10 One may argue that the relevant obligation is also deduced if the „equivalence rule“ between rights and duties like „right(Buyer,Seller,Action)<->duty(Seller,Buyer,Action)“ as in Hohfeld (see: note 1) is applied. However, it is to be noted that the duties of sellers are not always directly deduceable from the rights of buyers in law. In many cases in law, rights of one of the parties do not directly result in duties to another party. Law rather presupposes the exercise of rights for occurrence of the relevant obligations. In many case, law leaves the exercise of rights to the choice by the owner of the right. For example, CISG 45 specifies as follows: (1) If the seller fails to perform any of his obligations under the contract or this Convention, the buyer may: (a) exercise the rights provided in articles 46 to 52; (b) claim damages as provided in articles 74 to 77. It is not the case that every relevant obligation of the seller related to each remedy specified in articles 46 to 52 comes out at the time when the seller fails to perform any of his original contractual obligations, but the case that it comes out at the time when the buyer exercises the right selecting it from several rights of remedies. Therefore, we should interpret that law presupposes the fundamental meta-rule sentence like [3aa1].
- 11 This is a principle in Logic Programming, It means: the negation of a proposition is to be proven as true when the proof of the proposition is failed. See: the inference line (2) in Chapter 6.3
- 12 To CPF see: Yoshino (1997).
- 13 The concept of „cases“ here is in principle based on Case grammar (Fillmore, C. J. The Case for Case. In: Bach, Harms (Ed.), Universals in Linguistic Theory, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, New York, pp.1-88 (1968)). There are Agent case, Object case, Goal case, Location case, Time case and so on. In original CPF, CaseList is a list of pairs which represent case role (symbol) and filler. (Cf. Yoshino & Sakurai (1993), p. 298; Yoshino (1997), pp 82-88.) In this paper, case roles are eliminated for easy representation.
- 14 In the knowledge base, the rules are mounted with „sen“ predicate as below: sen(r0,[is_valid(I,[S,T])<-((become_valid(V,[S,T1])&before(T1,T))¬((become_null(N,[S,T2]),before(T2,T1))))]).
- 15 The validity of legal sentences is related not only to the time but also the place and the matter. For easy under-standing, we deal with here only the time case.